Isaiah Berlin - Russian Thinkers
- Название:Russian Thinkers
- Автор:
- Жанр:
- Издательство:неизвестно
- Год:0101
- ISBN:нет данных
- Рейтинг:
- Избранное:Добавить в избранное
-
Отзывы:
-
Ваша оценка:
Isaiah Berlin - Russian Thinkers краткое содержание
Russian Thinkers - читать онлайн бесплатно полную версию (весь текст целиком)
Интервал:
Закладка:
unceremonious, and exceedingly unreticent humour, there dwelt
the heart of a child. He had a curious, angular kind of charm, an
angular kind of delicacy . . . [but it was given] particularly to those
who were beginning, who were seeking after something, people who
were trying out their powers. They found a source of strength and
confidence in his advice. He took them into the most intimate communion with himself and with his ideas-which, nevertheless, did not stop him, at times, from using his full destructive, analytic
powers, from performing exceedingly painful, psychological experiments on these very same people at the very same time.
This vivid and sympathetic vignette tallies with the descriptions
left to us by Turgenev, Belinsky and others of Herzen's friends.
It is borne out, above all, by the impression which the reader
gains if he reads his own prose, his essays or the autobiographical
memoirs collected under the title My Post and Thoughts. The impression that it leaves is not conveyed even by Annenkov's devoted words.
The chief influence on Herzen as a young man in Moscow
University, as upon all the young Russian intellectuals of his time,
was of course that of Hegel. But although he was a fairly orthodox
Hegelian in his early years, he turned his Hegeliaqism into something
peculiar, personal to himself, very dissimilar from the theoretical conclusions which the more serious-minded and pedantic of his contemporaries deduced from that celebrated doctrine.
The chief effect upon him of Hegelianism seems to have been the
belief that no specific theory or single doctrine, no one interpretation
of life, above all, no simple, coherent, well-constructed sc-hemaneither the great French mechanistic models of the eighteenth century, nor the romantic German edifices of the nineteenth, nor the visions
of the great Utopians Saint-Simon, Fourier, Owen, nor the socialist
programmes of Cabet or Leroux or Louis Blanc-could conceivably
..
R U S S IAN T H I N KE R S
be true solutions to real problems, at least not i n the form i n which
they were preached.
He was sceptical if only because he believed (whether or not he
derived this view from Hegel) that there could not in principle be
any simple or final answer to any genuine human problem; that if a
question was serious and indeed agonising, the answer could never be
dear-cut and neat. Above all, it could never consist in some symmetrical set of conclusions, drawn by deductive means from a collection of self-evident axioms.
This disbelief begins in Herzen's early, forgotten essays which he
wrote at the beginning of the I 84os, on what he called dilettantism
and Buddhism in science; where he distinguishes two kinds of intellectual personality, against both of which he inveighs. One is that of the casual amateur who never sees the trees for the wood; who is terrified,
Herzen tells us, of losing his own precious individuality in too much
pedantic preoccupation with actual, detailed facts, and therefore
always skims over the surface without developing a capacity for real
knowledge; who looks at the facts, as it were, through a kind of
telescope, with the result that nothing ever gets articulated save
enormous, sonorous generalisations floating at random like so many
balloons.
The other kind of student-the Buddhist-is the person who escapes
from the wood by frantic absorption in the trees; who becomes an
intense student of some tiny set of isolated facts, which he views
through more and more powerful microscopes. Although such a man
might be deeply learned in some particular branch of knowledge,
almost invariably-and particularly if he is a German (and almost all
Herzen's gibes and insults are directed against the hated Germans,
and that despite the fact that he was half German himself)-he becomes
intolerably tedious, pompous and blindly philistine; above all, always
repellent as a human being.
Between these poles it is necessary to find some compromise, and
Herzen believed that if one studied life in a sober, detached, and
objective manner, one might perhaps be able to create some kind of
tension, a sort of dialer.tical compromise, between these opposite ideals;
for if neither or' them can be realised fully and equally, neither of them
should be altogether deserted ; only thus could human beings be made
capable of understanding life in some profounder fashion than if they
committed themselves recklessly to one or the other of the two
extremes.
ALEXAND E R H E RZEN
This ideal of detachment, moderation, compromise, dispassionate
objectivity which Herren at this early period of his life was preaching,
was something deeply incompatible with his temperament. And indeed,
not long after, he bursts forth with a great paean to partiality. He
declares that he knows that this will not be well received. There
are certain concepts which simply are not received in good societyrather like people who have disgraced themselves in some appalling way. Partiality is not something which is well thought of in comparison,
for example, with abstract justice. Nevertheless, nobody has ever said
anything worth saying unless he was deeply and passionately partial.
There follows a long and typically Russian diatribe against the
chilliness, meanness, impossibility and undesirability of remaining
objective, of being detached, of not committing oneself, of not
plunging into the stream of life. The passionate voice of his friend
Belinsky is suddenly audible in Herzen's writings in this phase of his
development.
The fundamental thesis which emerges at this time, and is then
developed throughout his later life with marvellous poetry and
imagination, is the terrible power over human lives of ideological
abstractions (I say poetry advisedly; for as Dostoevsky in later years
very truly said, whatever else might be said about Herzen, he was
certainly a Russian poet; which saved him in the eyes of this jaundiced
but, at times, uncannily penetrating critic: Herzen's views or mode of
life naturally found little favour in his eyes).
Herzen declares that any attempt to explain human conduct in
terms of, or to dedicate human beings to the service of, any abstraction,
be it never so noble-justice, progress, nationality-even if preached by
impeccable altruists like Mazzini or Louis Blanc or Mill, always leads
in the end to victimisation and human sacrifice. Men are not simple
enough, human lives and relationships are too complex for standard
formulas and neat solutions, and attempts to adapt individuals and fit
them into a rational schema, conceived in terms of a theoretical ideal,
be the motives for doing it never so lofty, always lead in the end to a
terrible maiming of human beings, to political vivisection on an ever
increasing scale. The process culminates in the liberation of some
only at the price of enslavement of others, and the replacing of an old
tyranny with a new and sometimes far more hideous one-by the
imposition of the slavery of universal socialism, for example, as a
remedy for the slavery of the universal Roman Church.
There is a typical piece of dialogue between Herzen and Louis
193
R U S SIAN T H INKERS
Blanc, the French socialist (whom . he respected greatly), which
Herzen quotes, and which shows the kind of levity with which
Herzen sometimes expressed his deepest convictions. The conversation
is described as having taken place in London somewhere in the early
sos. One day Louis Blanc observed to Herzen that human life was
a great social duty, 'that man must always sacrifice himself to society.
'Why?' I asked suddenly.
'How do you mean "Why?" [said Louis Blanc] -but surely the
whole purpose and mission of man is the well-being of society?'
'But it will never be attained if everyone makes sacrifices and
nobody enjoys himself.'
'You are playing with words.'
'The muddle-headedness of a barbarian,' I replied, laughing.
In this gay and apparently casual passage, Herzen embodies his
central principle-that the goal of life is life itself, that to sacrifice the
present to some vague and unpredictable future is a form of delusion
which leads to the destruction of all that alone is valuable in men and
societies-to the gratuitous sacrifice of the flesh and blood of live
human beings upon the altar of idealised abstractions.
Herzen is revolted by the central substance of what was being
preached by some of the best and purest-hearted men of his time,
particularly by socialists and utilitarians, namely, that vast suffering
in the present must be undergone for the sake of an ineffable felicity
in the future, that thousands of innocent men may be forced to die
that millions might be happy-battle cries that were common even in
those days, and of which a great deal more has been heard since. The
notion that there is a splendid future in store for humanity, that it is
guaranteed by history, and that it justifies the most appalling cruelties
in the present-this familiar piece of political eschatology, based on
belief in inevitable progress, seemed to him a fatal doctrine directed
against human life.
The profoundest and most sustained -and the most brilliantly
written-of all Herzen's statements on this topic is to be found in
the volume of essays which he called From tht Othtr Short, and wrote
as a memorial to his disillusionment with the European revolutions of
1 848 and 1 849. This great polemical masterpiece is Herzen's profession of faith and his political testament. Its tone and content are well conveyed in the characteristic (and celebrated) passage in which
he declares that one generation must not be condemned to the role of
194
ALEXAN D E R H E RZEN
being a mere means to the welfare of its remote descendants, which
is in any case none too certain. A distant goal is a cheat and a deception.
Real goals must be closer than that- 'at the very least the labourer's
wage or pleasure in work performed'. The end of each generation is
itself-each life has its own unique experience; the fulfilment of its
wants creates new needs, claims, new forms of life. Nature, he
declares (perhaps under the influence of Schiller), is careless of human
beings and their needs, and crushes them heedlessly. Has history a
plan, a libretto? If it did 'it would lose all interest, become . . . boring,
ludicrous'. There are no timetables, no cosmic patterns; there is only
the ' Row of life', passion, will, improvisation; sometimes roads exist,
sometimes not; where there is no road 'genius will blast a path'.
But what if someone were to ask, 'Supposing all this is suddenly
brought to an end? Supposing a comet strikes us and brings to an end
life on earth? Will history not be meaningless? Will all this talk suddenly
Читать дальшеИнтервал:
Закладка: